Front | Back |
3 reasons for
clarifying ground rules..
|
Involves
philosophically controversial concepts; need to understand foundations; inadequate
treatment in textbooks
|
2.1 What is a statement?
|
(a)
A meaningless string or words is not a statement [1]
(b)
Distinguishing statements from other meaningful word strings (sentences). [2, 3]
(c)
Interchangeability of statement & assertion.
(d)
Statements convey propositions (subject + predicate).
(e)
Every statement is either true or false.
|
consensus theory of
truth
|
Truth
is whatever everyone agrees to.
|
relativist theory
|
(which we met last week): according
to this view, there is no objective truth independent of what we
think or believe; we each have our own truths, which are true simply by virtue
of our taking them to be true. Hence, there is no point in trying to
determine whether something is true, because it can be true for me
but not for you. The obvious objection to this is that it is hard to
take seriously, because it allows the existence of contradictory states of
affairs. it is a contradiction.
|
Realist
|
According to this view, there is objective truth, and it is whatever
the facts are. So if one friend claims Agnes is the coordinator, and the other
claims she is not, the truth depends on the way the world is. In this theory,
truth is simply whatever is actually the case, whatever state of affairs
actually obtains in reality. By contrast, a statement or assertion is FALSE if
it claims something that is not the
case. Notice that this is not a question about how we know
|
Contingent statements
|
Most
statements are contingent: they may be true or false, and this depends on (is
contingent
upon) the way the world is, the facts. (contingent truths are sometimes
called
“synthetic” truths).
|
Non-contingent
statements
|
(i) Necessary truths -
tautologies (fr. Greek "tautos" = "identical")
(sometimes
also called “analytic truths” or “truisms”) Statements which are (a)
"true
by definition" [6] or (b) true by virtue of logical structure [7], & cannot
possibly
be false, because to deny them would be self-contradictory.
(ii) Self-contradictions
Statements
which are necessarily false (some say incoherent) - cannot possibly be
true.
A self-contradiction is the negation of a tautology. [8]
|
The functions of
language
|
(informative,
interrogative (asking questions), expressive. (indicating
how we feel), directive (giving instructions/commands), persuasive,
performative. (e.g.,
“I now pronounce you husband and wife”) è the concept of “speech acts” [we do
things
with language].
In evaluating arguments, we're concerned with statements or
assertions. This is called the informative function.
Language is used to convey information, to make statements, to claim things
(whether they are true or false).
|
Meaning - what is meaning and how does language mean things?
|
(a)
In language, the meaning of words (the connection between words and what they
stand
for) is largely conventional (i.e., it is arbitrary, based on agreement within a
language-speaking
community). Piaget showed that it takes young children a while to realize this
(e.g., they think that the sun must
be called the “sun”, because the name is part
of the object; they think that “train” is an example of a long word).
(b)
Therefore, in language, meaning is relational
(i.e., it involves a three-term relation
between
a word [the signifier], the referent of the word [the signified], and the person
who uses the word to refer
to the referent). For example, the word “sun” is used to refer
to
the yellow object in the sky by an English speaker.
(c)
There are two dimensions of meaning:
(i)
denotation =
everything referred to by a term
(ii)
connotation =
characteristics and associations (e.g., many words have
emotional
connotations).
(d)
Words with positive connotations = euphemisms (from Greek eu = “well”+ phemi
=
“to speak”).
|
(a) Requirements for
a good definition:
|
(1)
Be neither too broad nor too narrow
(2)
Avoid circularity.
(3)
Avoid being purely negative.
(4)
Avoid figurative language.
(5)
Avoid obscure or needlessly technical language.
(b)
Special definitional problems for psychology
(1)
Many terms used in psychology are controversial and “theoretically loaded”
(e.g.,
“anxiety”, “defense mechanism”, “self-concept”).
(2)
Many terms in psychology involve different/technical meanings of common
terms
(e.g., “reliability”, “validity”, “reinforcement”).
|
(a) Ambiguity
|
More
than one available interpretation. There are two types of ambiguity:
(i)
semantic ambiguity = a word or phrase has more than one meaning
(e.g., “He put the address
away in his briefcase”)
(ii)
syntactic ambiguity = the pattern or arrangement of words allows
for
more than one interpretation of the whole sentence (e.g., “A lecture
will
be given on deviant sexual behaviour in Lecture Theatre 1”).
(b)
Equivocation - exploiting ambiguity - switching between two meanings (e.g.,
Archie
equivocates on “cheating” and “being honest”)
|
(c) Vagueness:
|
:
unclear or fuzzy boundary for a word (e.g.
the word “bald” is vague,
because
it’s not clear where non-baldness ends and baldness begins).
|
(d) Overgenerality:
|
A
category that is very broad - e.g., overgeneral terms can be
exploited
to produce the "Barnum Effect" (“one
size fits all” e.g., horoscopes in
newspapers). (From P. T. Barnum: “A good circus should have a little
something for
everybody” and “There’s a sucker born every minute”).
|
(e) Labels
|
Oversimplifying
and stereotyping (e.g., “disabled”, “gay”, “refugee”)
|
(f) The "nominal
fallacy
|
-
naming x explains x (e.g., acrophobia explains fear of heights)
(g)
Reification (or hypostatization) = “thing-ification” - using language to invent
"things"
(e.g. “an ability”, “intelligence”,
“self-esteem”); turning something that is not a thing
into
a thing (just because we have a noun for it).
|